comparison of algebraic properties of cardinals and ordinals
Nice — here’s a compact, useful comparison of the algebraic properties of cardinals vs. ordinals, with definitions, the key laws, concrete examples, and the important caveats.
Quick definitions
- Ordinal: an order-type of a well-ordered set. Ordinal arithmetic depends on the order (how elements are arranged).
- Cardinal: a size (equivalence class under bijection) of a set. Cardinal arithmetic depends only on size, not on order.
Table of core properties (side-by-side)
Feature / Operation | Cardinals (cardinal arithmetic) | Ordinals (ordinal arithmetic) |
---|---|---|
Addition | Commutative, associative; identity 0 ; defined by disjoint union up to bijection. Example: ℵ0 + 1 = 1 + ℵ0 = ℵ0 . |
Not commutative in general; associative; identity 0 . Example: 1 + ω = ω but ω + 1 > ω . |
Multiplication | Commutative, associative; identity 1 ; distributive over addition. For infinite κ, κ·λ = max(κ,λ) in the usual cases (e.g. one factor infinite and nonzero). |
Not commutative; associative; identity 1 . Left-distributive over addition: α·(β+γ) = α·β + α·γ . Right-distributivity can fail: (α+β)·γ ≠ α·γ + β·γ in general. Example: 2·ω = ω , but (1·ω)+(1·ω)=ω+ω>ω . |
Exponentiation | Commutativity no longer meaningful; κ^λ is size of functions λ→κ . Can behave wildly; many values independent of ZFC (e.g. continuum hypothesis concerns 2^{ℵ0} ). |
Noncommutative and order-sensitive; defined by transfinite recursion. Very different qualitative behavior from cardinals. |
Commutativity of operations | Addition & multiplication commute (cardinal algebra is commutative). | Addition & multiplication do not commute in general. |
Distributivity | Multiplication distributes over addition (both sides). | Multiplication is left-distributive (α(β+γ)=αβ+αγ ) but not necessarily right-distributive. |
Cancellativity | Fails in general for infinite cardinals: e.g. κ + μ = κ + ν need not imply μ = ν ; also κ·μ = κ·ν doesn't imply cancellation. |
Fails strongly: e.g. ordinal cancellation is impossible in many cases (ω + 1 = ω + 1 trivial, but different summands can produce same sum in other contexts). |
Identities / inverses | Additive identity 0 . No additive inverses (no subtraction in general). Multiplicative identity 1 . No multiplicative inverses except 1 . |
Additive identity 0 , multiplicative identity 1 . No inverses (no subtraction or division in general). |
Order vs size sensitivity | Only size matters. Rearranging disjoint pieces does not change sum/product. | Order matters — e.g. appending on left vs right gives different ordinals. |
Algebraic structure viewpoint | Forms a commutative semiring (no negatives). Many regular laws hold; but cancellation and inverse laws fail for infinite cardinals. | A noncommutative semiring-like structure: associative +,· with identities, but many familiar ring laws fail (noncommutative, distribution only one-sided, no cancellation). |
Continuity at limits | Cardinal arithmetic often stabilizes for infinite cardinals (κ+κ = κ , κ·κ = κ for infinite κ). |
Ordinal operations are sensitive to limit ordinals; definitions use transfinite recursion and require separate rules at limit stages. |
Finer variants | — | Natural (Hessenberg) sum/product: alternate ordinal operations that are commutative and associative — useful for algebraic manipulations; coincide with ordinary sum/product for finite ordinals in simple ways. |
Independence / set-theory sensitivity | Cardinal exponentiation (e.g. 2^{ℵ0} ) is highly set-theoretic (CH independence). Some cardinal equalities require AC to get canonical representatives. |
Ordinal arithmetic is more absolute (less independent); facts about ordinals are generally settled in ZF (order-type theory). |
Concrete examples (to build intuition)
-
Ordinal asymmetry:
1 + ω = ω
(put a single element before ω — the tail still looks like ω)ω + 1 > ω
(put element after ω — you get a new largest element) -
Cardinal symmetry:
as sets,
ℵ0 ∪ {new}
has cardinalityℵ0
, soℵ0 + 1 = 1 + ℵ0 = ℵ0
. -
Multiplication contrast:
Ordinals:
2·ω = ω
(ω many copies of 2) butω·2 = ω + ω
(two blocks of size ω) — not equal. Cardinals:2·ℵ0 = ℵ0
andℵ0·2 = ℵ0
— both equal (multiplication commutes). - Natural (Hessenberg) sum/product: These ordinal variants are commutative. For many algebraic manipulations with ordinals one uses them, but ordinary ordinal addition/multiplication are the canonical order-type operations.
Why the differences arise (intuitive reasons)
-
Cardinals collapse all order information — only bijections matter. That forces commutativity:
|A ∪ B| = |B ∪ A|
. - Ordinals encode how the elements are arranged (first, second, limit positions). Arithmetic is defined by concatenation / repeated concatenation of well-ordered blocks, so left/right placement matters → noncommutativity and directional distributivity.
Algebraic language summary
- Cardinal numbers: a commutative semiring (with limits/behaviors that simplify for infinite sizes); many familiar algebraic laws hold but cancellation and inverses fail for infinite sizes; cardinal exponentiation is set-theory sensitive.
- Ordinal numbers: a noncommutative semiring-like structure under the usual ordinal + and ·; associative but noncommutative; multiplication distributes only on one side; sensitive to order and limit stages; additional commutative “natural” operations exist (Hessenberg) that restore commutativity.
Small checklist for proofs / exercises
- Prove ordinal addition is associative but not commutative (use concatenation / order-type arguments; give
1+ω
vsω+1
). - Prove cardinal addition is commutative by giving explicit bijection between
A ⊔ B
andB ⊔ A
. - Show
κ + λ = max(κ,λ)
for infinite cardinals under the usual hypotheses (exercise: construct injections in both directions). - Exhibit failure of right-distributivity for ordinals via the
2·ω
vs(1·ω)+(1·ω)
example. - Explore Cantor Normal Form (CNF) for ordinals: uniqueness + how CNF helps compute ordinal addition/multiplication.
If you want, I can:
- produce a one-page cheat sheet (LaTeX or printable) with the table + sample proofs, or
- walk through worked proofs of any specific law (e.g. why ordinal multiplication is left-distributive but not right-distributive), or
- show how the natural (Hessenberg) sum/product are defined and give examples.
Which follow-up would you like?
No comments:
Post a Comment